The origins of proof
by
Kona Macphee
|
|
What is proof?
Philosophers have argued for centuries about the answer to this question,
and how (and if!)
things can be proven; no doubt they will continue to do so! Mathematicians,
on the other hand, have been using "working definitions" of proof to advance
mathematical knowledge for equally long.
Starting in this issue, PASS Maths
is pleased to present a series of articles introducing some of the basic
ideas behind proof and logical reasoning and showing their importance in
mathematics.
In this article, we shall present a brief introduction to deductive
reasoning, and take a look at one of the earliest known examples of
mathematical proof.
Do the symbols below on the left match the descriptions on the right?
p | The greek letter "pi" |
x2 | x squared |
Öx | Square root of x |
If not, an alternative version of this page that should work with most
browsers is available here.
|
Deductive reasoning
Given
a set of facts that are known or assumed to be true, deductive reasoning
is a powerful way of extending that set of facts.
In deductive reasoning, we argue that if certain premises (P) are
known or assumed, a conclusion (C) necessarily follows from these.
For example, given the following (rather famous!) premises
P: All men are mortal.
P: Socrates is a man.
|
then the conclusion
follows via deductive reasoning. In this case, the deductive step is based
on the
logical principle that if A implies B, and A is true,
then B is true, a principle that mediaeval logicians called
modus ponens.
Of course,
deductive reasoning is not infallible: the premises may not be true,
or the line of reasoning itself may be wrong!
This is how you can
sometimes "prove" something that isn't actually true. There are any number
of ways of "proving" that 1 = 2, for example. Here's an old favourite:
Let a = b Thus, a2 = ab a2 + a2 = a2 + ab 2a2 = a2 + ab 2a2 - 2ab = a2 + ab - 2ab 2a2 - 2ab = a2 - ab
Rewrite this as: 2(a2 - ab) = 1(a2 - ab) Dividing both sides by a2 - ab, we thus have: 2 = 1
QED.
|
|
Can you spot the flaw in the argument?
Now, if a conclusion doesn't follow from its premises, the argument is said to
be invalid and no reliable judgement can be made about whether the
conclusion is true, regardless of whether or not the premises are true.
If the argument is valid but the premises are not
true, then again the conclusion may or may not be true, but the argument
can't help us decide this.
Finally, if the argument is
valid and the premises are true, then the argument is described as
sound, and we deem the conclusion to be true.
From a pragmatic point of view, we can be said to have proved something
if we can find a sound argument for it.
Table 1 summarises these different kinds of deductive arguments,
and table 2 provides an example of each.
| C doesn't follow | C follows |
P untrue
|
Invalid
|
Valid, unsound
|
P true
|
Invalid
|
Valid, sound
|
Table 1: Different kinds of deductive arguments.
Invalid, false premises
P: Fish are mammals.
P: Fish are warm-blooded.
- - - - -
C: Mammals are warm-blooded.
|
Valid, unsound
P: Mammals are cold-blooded.
P: Humans are mammals.
- - - - -
C: Humans are cold-blooded.
|
Invalid, true premises
P: Fish are cold-blooded.
P: Humans are not fish.
- - - - -
C: Humans are warm-blooded.
|
Valid, sound
P: Humans are warm-blooded.
P: Fishermen are human.
- - - - -
C: Fishermen are warm-blooded.
|
Table 2: Some example deductive arguments.
As the two invalid arguments in table 2 suggest, the conclusion of an
invalid argument doesn't necessarily have to be false - it's just
unproven by that particular argument!
In the beginning: Euclid's geometry
Euclid was born about 365 BC in Alexandria, Egypt, and died
about 300 BC. Little is known of his life other than that he taught
mathematics in Alexandria.
Euclid wrote a number of treatises, but the most famous is his Elements,
a work on geometry that has been used as a textbook for over 2000 years!
Rather than representing Euclid's original work, the Elements are now
thought to be a summary of the geometrical knowledge current during
his time. However, they represent one of the earliest uses of proof in
the history of mathematics.
In his Elements, Euclid begins with a list of twenty-three
definitions
describing things like points, lines, plane surfaces, circles, obtuse
and acute angles and so on (here, these are given in the
appendix).
Euclid's definitions are neither true nor false: they simply act as a
kind of dictionary, explaining what is meant by the various terms
he will be using.
He then presents a set of ten assumptions.
Five of these are not specific to geometry, and he calls them
common notions:
- 1. Things which are equal to the same thing are also equal to one another.
- 2. If equals be added to equals, the wholes are equal.
- 3. If equals be subtracted from equals, the remainders are equal.
- 4. Things which coincide with one another are equal to one another.
- 5. The whole is greater than the part.
The other five assumptions are specifically geometric,
and he calls them postulates :
- 1. It is possible to draw a straight line from any point to any point.
- 2. It is possible to produce a finite straight line continuously in a
straight line.
- 3. It is possible to describe a circle with any centre and distance.
- 4. All right angles are equal to one another.
- 5. If a straight line falling on two straight lines make the interior angles on the same side less than two right angles,
the two straight lines, if produced indefinitely, meet on that
side on which are the angles less than the two right angles.
(Note that Playfair's Axiom (originally due to
Proclus)
that "through a point not on a
given line, there passes not more than one parallel to the line" is a
rather neater way of expressing postulate 5! In addition, in the nineteenth
century,
Legendre went on to show
that postulate 5 is equivalent to the postulate that "the sum of the angles
of a triangle is equal to two right angles").
Together, these common notions
and postulates represent the axioms of Euclid's geometry. An axiom
is a logical principle which is assumed to be true rather than proven,
and which can be used as a premise in a deductive argument.
Euclid's set of axioms, or axiomatic system,
represents a collection of "first principles" from which other principles can be
produced using deductive reasoning. Of course, any deductive arguments
are only sound if Euclid's common notions and postulates really are true!
An example proposition and proof
Euclid goes on in his Elements to present various geometric
propositions, and shows them to be true using deductive inference
within his axiomatic system.
An example is proposition 6:
"If in a triangle two angles be equal to one another, the sides
which subtend the equal angles will also be equal to one another."
Euclid's actual proof of this proposition is as follows:
Figure 1: Euclid's proposition 6.
"Let ABC be a triangle having the angle ABC equal to
the angle ACB;
I say the side AB is also equal to the
side AC.
For, if AB is unequal to AC, one of them
is greater.
Let AB be greater; and from AB the greater,
let DB be cut off equal to AC the less; let DC be joined.
Then, since DB is equal to AC, and BC is common, the two
sides DB, BC are equal to the two sides AC, CB respectively,
and the angle DBC is equal to the angle ACB.
Therefore, the base DC is equal to the base AB, and the triangle DBC
will be equal to the triangle ACB, the less to the greater,
which is absurd. Therefore AB is not unequal to AC; it is therefore
equal to it."
If you have a Java capable browser you can try a
dynamic version of this drawing here.
Are Euclid's postulates true?
Both the Greeks of Euclid's time, and later Arabic mathematicians, had an
intuition that the fifth postulate could actually be proven using the
definitions and common notions and the
first four postulates.
Many attempts to prove the fifth postulate in this manner were made, and
often a putative proof
would be accepted for a long period before being shown to be flawed.
Typically, the flawed proofs contained a "circular argument": in one way
or another, they assumed that what they were trying to prove (the
fifth postulate) was true in order to prove it!
In fact, the fifth postulate is not derivable from the other postulates
and notions, and nor is it universally true. Mathematicians
continued to be fascinated by the fifth postulate throughout the centuries,
but it was not until the nineteenth and twentieth centuries (through the
efforts of a
number of famous mathematicians including
Legendre,
Gauss,
Bolyai,
Lobachevsky,
Riemann,
Beltrami and
Klein), that we came to know about geometries (called non-Euclidian
geometries) where the fifth postulate is not true.
The fifth postulate can be shown to be true in a plane (or
Euclidian) geometry. However, there are many other geometries where
it is not true. Surprisingly enough, this is easy to illustrate! Consider
the simple case of a sphere's surface.
It is impossible to draw a true straight line on a
sphere without leaving the surface, So
in spherical geometry the Euclidean idea of a line becomes a great
circle. Thinking of the Earth, any line of longitude is a great
circle - as is the equator. In fact the shortest path between any two
points on a sphere is a great circle. (More generally, a minimal path
on any surface is known as a geodesic.)
One of the consequences of Euclid's first four postulates is that if
two different lines cross, they meet at a single point. This presents
a small problem on the sphere, since distinct great circles always
cross at two antipodal points! Two lines of longitude always cross at
both the North and the South Pole!
But remember, we haven't yet said what the spherical analogue
of a Euclidean point is! All we have to do is define a
point in
spherical geometry to be a pair of antipodal points and the
problem promptly disappears.
According to Euclid's definition number 23,
"Parallel straight lines are straight lines which, being
in the same plane and being produced indefinitely in both
directions, do not meet one another in either direction".
Given these definitions, it is easy to see that Euclid's first four
postulates still make good sense. The fifth postulate, however, fails
because it is impossible to draw two different
lines that do not meet. In spherical geometry there are no
parallel lines!
One of the consequences of the failure of the 5th postulate is that it
is no longer true that the sum of the angles of a triangle is always
180 degrees.
In fact, there's a famous lateral-thinking puzzle that depends
implicitly on this non-Euclidian geometry:
A hunter leaves his house one morning and walks one mile due south.
He then walks one mile due west and shoots a bear, before walking a mile
due north
back to his house.
What colour is the bear?
|
Euclid and deductive reasoning
The story of Euclidian geometry, and the subsequent discovery of non-Euclidian
geometries, show the benefits and disadvantages of using deductive reasoning
from axioms as a proof system.
Using his definitions, common notions and postulates as an axiomatic system,
Euclid was able to produce deductive proofs of a number of important geometric
propositions. His axioms and proofs have been a useful set of tools for many
subsequent generations of mathematicians, and show how powerful and beneficial
deductive reasoning can be!
However, the long and painful process of discovering non-Euclidian geometries
has shown one of the limitations of deductive reasoning in an axiomatic
system: that any proof is only as good as the axioms it starts off with!
In the Euclidian plane, Euclid's fifth postulate is true, and his valid proofs
are sound. In non-Euclidian geometries such as the
surface of a sphere, however, the fifth postulate is not true, and
Euclid's proofs are therefore unsound.
Bibliography
About the author
Kona Macphee
is a member of the PASS Maths editorial team.
Image © Kerry Rodden 1998
- 1. A point is that which has no part.
- 2. A line is breadthless length.
- 3. The extremities of a line are points.
- 4. A straight line is a line which lies evenly with the points on itself.
- 5. A surface is that which has length and breadth only.
- 6. The extremities of a surface are lines.
- 7. A plane surface is a surface which lies evenly with the
straight lines on itself.
- 8. A plane angle is the inclination to one another of two lines in
a plane which meet one another and do not lie in a straight
line.
- 9. And when the lines containing the angle are straight, the
angle is called rectilineal.
- 10. When a straight line set up on a straight line makes the
adjacent angles equal to one another, each of the equal
angles is right, and the straight line standing on the other is
called a perpendicular to that on which it stands.
- 11. An obtuse angle is an angle greater than a right angle.
- 12. An acute angle is an angle less than a right angle.
- 13. A boundary is that which is an extremity of anything.
- 14. A figure is that which is contained by any boundary or boundaries.
- 15. A circle is a plane figure contained by one line such that all
the straight lines falling upon it from one point among those
lying within the figure are equal to one another;
- 16. And the point is called the centre of the circle.
- 17. A diameter of the circle is any straight line drawn through
the centre and terminated in both directions by the
circumference of the circle, and such a straight line also
bisects the circle.
- 18. A semicircle is the figure contained by the diameter and the
circumference cut off by it. And the centre of the semicircle
is the same as that of the circle.
- 19. Rectilineal figures are those which are contained by straight
lines, trilateral figures being those contained by three,
quadrilateral those contained by four, and multilateral those
contained by more than four straight lines.
- 20. Of trilateral figures, an equilateral triangle is that which has
its three sides equal, an isosceles triangle that which has two
of its sides alone equal, and a scalene triangle that which has
its three sides unequal.
- 21. Further, of trilateral figures, a right-angled triangle is that
which has a right angle, an obtuse-angled triangle that
which has an obtuse angle, and an acute-angled triangle that
which has its three angles acute.
- 22. Of quadrilateral figures, a square is that which is both
equilateral and right-angled; an oblong that which is
right-angled but not equilateral; a rhombus that which is
equilateral but not right-angled; and a rhomboid that which
has its opposite sides and angles equal to one another but is
neither equilateral nor right-angled. And let quadrilaterals
other than these be called trapezia.
- 23. Parallel straight lines are straight lines which, being
in the same plane and being produced indefinitely in both
directions, do not meet one another in either direction.
|